text
stringlengths 0
174
|
---|
code by which a listener could decode them into a message. A typical example is
|
"Imaginary Landscape no. 4", the polyradio piece described in Chapter VI. I may not
|
be doing Cage justice, but to me it seems that much of his work has been directed at
|
bringing meaninglessness into music, and in some sense, at making that meaninglessness
|
have meaning. Aleatoric music is a typical exploration in that direction. (Incidentally,
|
chance music is a close cousin to the much later notion of "happenings" or "be-in"' s.)
|
There are many other contemporary composers who are following Cage’s lead, but few
|
with as much originality. A piece by Anna Lockwood, called "Piano Burning", involves
|
just that-with the strings stretched to maximum tightness, to make them snap as loudly as
|
possible; in a piece by LaMonte Young, the noises are provided by shoving the piano all
|
around the stage and through obstacles, like a battering ram.
|
Art in this century has gone through many convulsions of this general type. At
|
first there was the abandonment of representation, which was genuinely revolutionary:
|
the beginnings of abstract art. A gradual swoop from pure representation to the most
|
highly abstract patterns is revealed in the work of Piet Mondrian. After the world was
|
used to nonrepresentational art, then surrealism came along. It was a bizarre about-face,
|
something like neoclassicism in music, in which extremely representational art was
|
"subverted" and used for altogether new reasons: to shock, confuse, and amaze. This
|
school was founded by Andre Breton, and was located primarily in France; some of its
|
more infl uential members were Dali, Magritte, de Chirico, Tanguy.
|
Magritte's Semantic Illusions
|
Of all these artists, Magritte was the most conscious of the symbol-object mystery (which
|
I see as a deep extension of the use-mention distinction). He uses it to evoke powerful
|
responses in viewers, even if the viewers do not verbalize the distinction this way. For
|
example, consider his very strange variation on the theme of still life, called Common
|
Sense (Fig. 137).
|
Here, a dish filled with fruit, ordinarily the kind of thing represented inside a still life, is
|
shown sitting on top of a blank canvas. The conflict between the symbol and the real is
|
great. But that is not the full irony, for of course the whole thing is itself just a painting-in
|
fact, a still life with nonstandard subject matter.
|
Magritte's series of pipe paintings is fascinating and perplexing. Consider The
|
Two Mysteries (Fig. 138). Focusing on the inner painting, you get the message that
|
symbols and pipes are different. Then your glance moves upward to the "real” pipe
|
floating in the air-you perceive that it is real, while the other one is just a symbol. But that
|
is of course totally wrong: both of them are on the same flat surface before your eyes.
|
The idea that one pipe is in a twice-nested painting, and therefore somehow "less real"
|
than the other pipe, is a complete fallacy. Once you are willing to "enter the room", you
|
have already been tricked: you’ve fallen for image as reality. To be consistent in your
|
gullibility, you should happily go one level further down, and confuse image-within-
|
image with reality. The only way not to be sucked in is to see both pipes merely as
|
colored smudges on a surface a few inches in front of your nose. Then, and only then, do
|
you appreciate the full meaning of the written message "Ceci West pas une pipe”-but
|
ironically, at the very instant everything turns to smudges, the writing too turns to
|
smudges, thereby losing its meaning! In other words, at that instant, the verbal message
|
of the painting self-destructs in a most Godelian way.
|
The Air and the Song (Fig. 82), taken from a series by Magritte, accomplishes all
|
that The Two Mysteries does, but in one level instead of two. My drawings Smoke Signal
|
and Pipe Dream (Figs. 139 and 140) constitute "Variations on a Theme of Magritte". Try
|
staring at Smoke Signal for a while. Before long, you should be able to make out a hidden
|
message saying, "Ceci n’est pas un message". Thus, if you find the message, it denies
|
itself-yet if you don't, you miss the point entirely. Because of their indirect self-snuffing,
|
my two pipe pictures can be loosely mapped onto Godel’s G-thus giving rise to a
|
"Central Pipemap", in the same spirit as the other "Central Xmaps": Dog, Crab, Sloth.
|
A classic example of use-mention confusion in paintings is the occurrence of a
|
palette in a painting. Whereas the palette is an illusion created by the representational
|
skill of the painter, the paints on the painted palette are literal daubs of paint from the
|
artist's palette. The paint plays itself-it does not symbolize anything else. In Don
|
Giovanni, Mozart exploited a related trick: he wrote into the score explicitly the sound of
|
an orchestra tuning up. Similarly, if I want the letter T to play itself (and not symbolize
|
me), I put T directly into my text; then I enclose T between quotes. What results is "I"
|
(not T, nor "T"). Got that?
|
The "Code" of Modern Art
|
A large number of influences, which no one could hope to pin down completely, led to
|
further explorations of the symbol-object dualism in art. There is no doubt that John
|
Cage, with his interest in Zen, had a profound influence on art as well as on music. His
|
friends jasper Johns and Robert Rauschenberg both explored the distinction between
|
objects and symbols by using objects as symbols for themselves-or, to flip the coin, by
|
using symbols as objects in themselves. All of this was perhaps intended to break down
|
the notion that art is one step removed from reality-that art speaks in "code", for which
|
the viewer must act as interpreter. The idea was to eliminate the step of interpretation and
|
let the naked object simply be, period. ("Period"-a curious case of use-mention blur.)
|
However, if this was the intention, it was a monumental flop, and perhaps had to be.
|
Any time an object is exhibited in a gallery or dubbed a "work", it acquires an
|
aura of deep inner significance-no matter how much the viewer has been warned not to
|
look for meaning. In fact, there is a backfiring effect whereby the more that viewers are
|
told to look at these objects without mystification, the more mystified the viewers get.
|
After all, if a
|
wooden crate on a museum floor is just a wooden crate on a museum floor, then why
|
doesn't the janitor haul it out back and throw it in the garbage? Why is the name of an
|
artist attached to it? Why did the artist want to demystify art? Why isn't that dirt clod out
|
front labeled with an artist's name? Is this a hoax? Am I crazy, or are artists crazy? More
|
and more questions flood into the viewer's mind; he can't help it. This is the "frame
|
effect" which art-Art-automatically creates. There is no way to suppress the wonderings
|
in the minds of the curious.
|
Of course, if the purpose is to instill a Zen-like sense of the world as devoid of
|
categories and meanings, then perhaps such art is merely intended to serve-as does
|
intellectualizing about Zen-as a catalyst to inspire the viewer to go out and become
|
acquainted with the philosophy which rejects "inner meanings" and embraces the world
|
Subsets and Splits
No community queries yet
The top public SQL queries from the community will appear here once available.